Photo by Elisa Photography on Unsplash

In the intricate tapestry of contemporary discourse surrounding selfhood and well-being, the notion of self-centeredness occupies a central and nuanced position. Often misconstrued within the facile dichotomy of egocentrism and genuine self-care, the discernment of self-centeredness as a complex paradigm warrants intellectual scrutiny. This introductory exploration endeavors to unravel the epistemic divergence inherent in the conceptual framework, shedding light on the intricate interplay between self-centeredness and the authentic pursuit of individual welfare. By navigating the intricate contours of this discourse, we embark on a cognitive journey aimed at deconstructing the prevailing narratives surrounding selfhood, thus laying the groundwork for a more nuanced understanding of self-centeredness as distinctly removed from the ethos of genuine self-care.

Exploration of the Philosophical Notions Surrounding the Concept of Self

The Western philosophical outlook characterizes philosophy as the pursuit of knowledge, primarily intellectual, centered on humanity's relationship with the external universe—encompassing matter and motion perceived by the five senses. In Eastern philosophy, especially in Vedanta, the term philosophy gives way to Brahma Vidya. Here, the focus shifts towards recognizing Brahman as the all-encompassing Self, establishing self-realization as the fundamental purpose of human existence. This underscores a fundamental distinction between Eastern and Western traditions: the former prioritizes self-awakening and transcending the ego, while the latter seeks knowledge of the world to comprehend humanity's position within it.

Within this paradigm, the Bhagavad Gita is regarded as a wellspring of profound wisdom. Its teachings not only broaden the mind but also offer practical guidance on achieving life's objectives. The emphasis lies in acquiring equanimity, internal tranquility, and mastering the art, science, and craftsmanship of mindful, skillful, and selfless actions. Swami Rama succinctly articulates this by underscoring the difference between the real Self (consciousness) and the mere self (ego). Grasping and grounding oneself in the essential nature, Atman, enables living in the world without succumbing to adverse influences.

In this context, the interaction between the real Self and the mere self involves the antahkarana, our internal instrument, crucial for both internal and external facets of life. Failing to grasp this internal dynamic undermines the dual objectives of worldly living and Self Realization. Therefore, a profound exploration of our psychological life becomes imperative to emancipate ourselves from emotional entanglements, ego-driven preoccupations, and self-delusions, facilitating the fullest realization of consciousness.

Some of the Western philosophers and their understanding of self

Descartes, having scrutinized his radical skepticism, endeavors to discern the foundations of knowledge. Recognizing subjective self-awareness as the most dependable, he embarks on a quest for a profound comprehension of the self.

His journey commences with the Cogito argument, asserting that the act of doubt itself establishes existence. Though not initially expressed as "Cogito, ergo sum" in the Meditations, Descartes contends that this famous statement encapsulates an intuitive leap rather than a syllogism, as a thinking entity must inherently exist.

Having confirmed his existence, Descartes ponders the nature of his being, identifying himself as a thinking thing. Delving into substance theory, he defines the mind as an independent substance with thought as its essence and various modes such as doubting and affirming.

To further understand the mind, Descartes examines a piece of wax, realizing that sensory perceptions alone do not capture its true nature. He concludes that his mind, through judgment, comprehends the wax's essence as an extended, flexible substance, highlighting the limited value of senses.

From this exploration, Descartes deduces that his mind is more knowable than anything external. However, a paradox arises as his knowledge of his mind's ability to perceive properties is itself a property, challenging the solidity of his conclusion.

In summary, Descartes navigates through doubt, self-awareness, and the nature of the mind, unraveling philosophical intricacies and confronting the limitations of sensory perception in understanding the self and the external world.

Immaneul Kant's exploration of consciousness of self involves seven key theses. Firstly, he distinguishes two types: empirical self-consciousness, involving inner sense, and transcendental apperception, associated with performing acts of apperception. The sources and nature of these two types differ.

The representational base of consciousness of oneself and one's states, according to Kant, arises from ordinary acts of synthesis, providing a foundation for awareness of both representational states and oneself as the subject. This, he argues, leads to a unique form of consciousness that encompasses spontaneity, rationality, and freedom.

In the realm of inner sense, Kant contends that consciousness is limited to how one appears to oneself, lacking knowledge of one's true nature. This aligns with his concerns about the implications for faith and morality if one could prove a priori that all thinking beings are simple substances.

Kant's treatment of consciousness as subject involves a focus on the referential machinery used to obtain it. He suggests that consciousness of self doesn't require identifying or ascribing properties to oneself, anticipating later philosophical insights into self-reference without identification.

In the consciousness of self as subject, Kant introduces the idea that nothing manifold is given, emphasizing a bare consciousness of self without specific properties. This unique form of self-consciousness remains constant regardless of other experiences.

Crucially, Kant distinguishes between consciousness of self and true knowledge of self. He argues that even though one can be conscious of oneself, this bare consciousness doesn't yield genuine knowledge of one's true nature.

Finally, Kant asserts that when conscious of oneself as subject, there is a simultaneous awareness of being the "single common subject" across various representations. This unity of self-consciousness implies an undivided sense of identity across diverse experiences.

These theses collectively offer a nuanced understanding of consciousness of self in Kant's philosophy, touching on empirical and transcendental dimensions, the limitations of inner sense, the nature of reference to oneself, and the distinction between consciousness and knowledge of self.

Essentialism, originating from Aristotle, asserts that everything possesses an essence—a core set of properties crucial for its identity. This concept, applied to human existence, suggests predetermined life purposes. However, existentialism, championed by thinkers like Sartre in response to events like World War II, challenges this by proposing that individuals determine their essence.

This movement contends that existence precedes essence, emphasizing personal responsibility in shaping one's purpose. The burden of such freedom, as Sartre notes, can be overwhelming, leading to existential crises. The absurdity of life, according to existentialists, lies in seeking answers in a world inherently devoid of absolute truths or guidelines. Living authentically, a concept coined by Sartre, involves embracing personal responsibility and rejecting "bad faith," which is conforming to external definitions of meaning. In essence, existentialism asserts that individuals create their own purpose, making the answer to life's meaning both simple and infinitely complex.

Through these simplified overviews, it becomes clearer how these individualistic philosophies impact contemporary popular individualistic perspectives.

Hegel's subject-object relationship

Hegel's subject-object relationship is a philosophical concept where the subject and object are interconnected and mutually constitutive. In Hegelian dialectics, the subject (consciousness) and the object (external reality) are interdependent; each shapes and defines the other in an ongoing, dynamic process. This relationship evolves through a dialectical movement, leading to a higher synthesis that transcends the initial opposition. It's a key aspect of Hegel's idealism, emphasizing the active role of consciousness in shaping reality and the continuous development of knowledge and understanding.

In Hegelian philosophy, the concept of "the one and the other" is often associated with the dialectical process of negation and mediation. It's part of Hegel's broader exploration of how contradictions and oppositions lead to a higher synthesis.

In simple terms, the dialectical movement involves an initial "one" or thesis, which then encounters its opposite or "other," the antithesis. The conflict between the thesis and antithesis results in negation, but instead of complete annihilation, this process leads to a synthesis that incorporates elements of both the original thesis and antithesis.

So, "the one and the other" captures the dynamic interplay between opposing forces in Hegel's dialectical method, ultimately driving the development of ideas, concepts, and reality itself toward greater complexity and understanding.

Jean-Paul Sartre, an existentialist philosopher, approached the subject-object relationship in the context of his existentialist ontology. Sartre rejected traditional philosophical dualisms and emphasized human freedom and individual responsibility.

For Sartre, the subject-object relationship is explored through his concept of "consciousness" and "being-in-itself" or "being-for-itself." Consciousness, or "being-for-itself," is characterized by its freedom, choice, and intentional nature. On the other hand, the "being-in-itself" refers to the external world or objects that exist independently of consciousness.

Sartre argued that the subject-object relationship is dynamic and characterized by tension. Consciousness, in its pursuit of freedom, confronts the inert, fixed nature of objects. The world of objects, or "being-in-itself," resists the freedom and spontaneity of consciousness. This tension between consciousness and the external world is a fundamental aspect of human existence.

In Sartrean existentialism, individuals are seen as continuously engaged in the process of defining themselves through their choices and actions, and the subject-object relationship reflects this ongoing struggle for authenticity and self-definition.

Emmanuel Levinas: Beliefs in ethics

Emmanuel Levinas critiqued Western philosophy for what he perceived as a failure to adequately address ethical concerns and the fundamental human experience of encountering "the Other." Levinas argued that traditional Western philosophy, with its emphasis on rationality and objectivity, tended to overlook or downplay the ethical dimension of human existence.

Levinas believed that philosophers like Immanuel Kant and Edmund Husserl, while making valuable contributions, fell short in recognizing the ethical significance of encountering another human being. He contended that Western philosophy often prioritized abstract concepts, universals, and the self, neglecting the profound ethical implications of face-to-face interactions with others.

Levinas was critical of a philosophy that reduced the Other to an object of knowledge or a concept, emphasizing the need to recognize the ethical responsibility inherent in acknowledging the uniqueness and vulnerability of each human being. He argued for a shift from an ontology centered on Being to an ethics centered on the face-to-face encounter, challenging the prevailing philosophical paradigms of his time.

In essence, Levinas saw Western philosophy as a failure because he believed it did not adequately address the ethical imperative of recognizing and responding to the humanity of the Other.

Levinas's emphasis on the ethical encounter with "the Other" is illustrated in his engagement with Fyodor Dostoevsky's novel, "The Brothers Karamazov." In particular, Levinas found resonance in Dostoevsky's exploration of moral responsibility and the profound impact of one's actions on others.

In "The Brothers Karamazov," the character Ivan Karamazov famously presents the "Grand Inquisitor" parable, where Christ returns to Earth during the Spanish Inquisition. In this narrative, the Grand Inquisitor rejects Christ's message of freedom and love, arguing that humanity prefers security and authority over the burdens of individual responsibility.

Levinas, drawing on Dostoevsky's exploration, saw a parallel to his own concerns about the neglect of ethical responsibility in Western philosophy. The rejection of Christ's message represents a failure to recognize the ethical call of the Other, choosing instead the comfort of established structures.

Levinas admired Dostoevsky for probing the depths of human existence and moral choices, emphasizing the ethical demand placed upon individuals in their encounters with others. Both thinkers shared a concern for the ethical implications of human relationships, challenging philosophical traditions that overlooked or dismissed the ethical dimension of existence.

In this way, Dostoevsky's exploration of moral dilemmas and the ethical responsibility of individuals resonated with Levinas's critique of Western philosophy's failure to adequately address the ethical encounter with "the Other."

While Emmanuel Levinas engaged with phenomenology, he also critiqued certain aspects of it, particularly its tendency to prioritize the self and objective analysis over the ethical implications of human relationships.

Levinas was initially influenced by phenomenologists like Edmund Husserl, and he studied under Husserl's student, Martin Heidegger. However, Levinas's philosophical trajectory diverged from classical phenomenology. Phenomenology, as developed by Husserl and others, seeks to describe and analyze the structures of consciousness and experience. It often involves a reduction to the subjective, intending ego.

Levinas appreciated phenomenology's emphasis on describing lived experience, but he felt that it fell short in addressing the ethical dimension of encounters with others. In his own philosophical works, Levinas argued for a shift from a focus on the self (ego) to the recognition of the Other as an independent, unique, and irreducible presence.

Levinas's criticism of phenomenology is encapsulated in his idea of the "face-to-face" encounter. He argued that the ethical demand arises from encountering the face of the Other, disrupting the self-centered orientation inherent in traditional phenomenology. For Levinas, the face of the Other calls us to responsibility and interrupts the self's quest for understanding and mastery.

In summary, while Levinas engaged with phenomenological methods and concepts, he expanded phenomenology's scope by emphasizing the ethical implications of encountering the Other, challenging the conventional focus on subjective analysis in phenomenology.

Individualism and virtue signaling

Individualism and virtue signaling are concepts often discussed in the context of societal values and behaviors.

Individualism generally refers to the emphasis on individual rights, autonomy, and self-reliance. It celebrates the uniqueness and agency of individuals, often prioritizing personal freedoms and choices. While individualism can promote independence and innovation, critics argue that an excessive focus on the individual may lead to social fragmentation and a lack of collective responsibility.

Virtue signaling, on the other hand, refers to the public expression of opinions or actions with the primary goal of demonstrating one's moral or virtuous stance, often on social or political issues. While expressing virtuous values is not inherently negative, the term "virtue signaling" is sometimes used pejoratively when the expressed values are perceived as insincere or intended for social approval rather than genuine commitment.

In the intersection of these concepts, one might argue that excessive individualism can contribute to a culture where virtue signaling becomes more prevalent. In a society that highly values individual expression, individuals may feel compelled to publicly showcase their virtuous positions as a way to distinguish themselves or gain social approval.

It's important to note that discussions around individualism and virtue signaling are nuanced, and perspectives on their implications can vary widely based on cultural, social, and philosophical contexts.

Gen Z's macro vs micro trend

In the context of Gen Z's attitudes towards macro (societal) and micro (personal) aspects, the rise of digitalization has played a significant role.

Macro Attitudes:

  1. Digital World Impact: Gen Z, having grown up in a digital age, generally embraces the opportunities and conveniences offered by technology. The digital world has facilitated connectivity, access to information, and new forms of expression.
  2. Societal Activism: There's a notable trend of heightened social awareness and activism within Gen Z. Issues like climate change, social justice, and equality are prominent concerns, and digital platforms provide avenues for voicing opinions and organizing movements.

Micro Attitudes:

  1. Digital Interaction: Face-to-face interaction may take a backseat as digital communication becomes more prevalent. Gen Z is often comfortable with digital communication tools, which can impact traditional forms of personal interaction.
  2. Responsibility in Communication: The digital landscape allows for the rapid spread of information, but it also brings challenges. Gen Z may engage in throwing around big words or opinions without the same level of accountability often associated with face-to-face communication.

Challenges:

  1. Disconnect: The reliance on digital communication might contribute to a sense of disconnection in more traditional, interpersonal relationships.
  2. Digital Echo Chambers: Online spaces can sometimes reinforce existing beliefs, limiting exposure to diverse perspectives.
  3. Responsibility Concerns: There's a risk of making strong statements without fully understanding the consequences, given the speed at which information can spread online.

Positives:

  1. Global Connectivity: Gen Z's digital engagement allows for global connections and collaborations.
  2. Amplified Voices: Digital platforms empower individuals to have their voices heard on a larger scale.
  3. Information Access: Gen Z has unprecedented access to information, contributing to a well-informed and aware generation.

In conclusion, while the digital world offers numerous advantages, it also presents challenges. Gen Z's attitudes reflect a complex interplay between embracing the opportunities of a digital era and addressing the potential pitfalls, especially concerning face-to-face interaction and the responsible use of the powerful digital tools at their disposal.

Online intensifies individualism

The rise of the digital world has undeniably intensified individualism, particularly within the context of Gen Z. The macro attitudes of this generation reflect a heightened sense of societal awareness and activism, often channeled through digital platforms. While this global connectivity allows for the amplification of individual voices and the pursuit of collective causes, the micro attitudes reveal a shift towards digital interaction, potentially diminishing the importance of face-to-face connections.

The ease of expressing opinions online, coupled with the speed of information dissemination, has empowered individuals to voice their perspectives, contributing to a more individualistic ethos. However, this freedom comes with challenges, as the digital landscape can create echo chambers and allow for the dissemination of strong opinions without the same level of responsibility associated with traditional communication.

In navigating this digital era, Gen Z faces a delicate balance between leveraging the advantages of individual expression and social activism online while recognizing the importance of meaningful face-to-face interactions and the responsibility that comes with the words they choose to share in the vast digital realm. The online world, with its potential to intensify individualism, presents both opportunities and challenges that this generation continues to grapple with as they shape the evolving landscape of societal and personal connections.

.    .    .

Discus